Sunday, January 31, 2010

Euthyphro Dilemma in the Philosophy of Religion

The Euthyphro Dilemma Explained

As promised, I said I would post the problem of evil as explained by Plato in the Euthyphro Dilemma. I had previously stated that I would post this for my YouTube watchers. I got this quick summary from the Wikipedia website. I know it's not the best as far as research goes, but it is good for acquainting oneself with the argument(s). I will also post my video on the bottom. (Note: Blue ink lettering is the article.)

The dilemma can be modified to apply to philosophical theism, where it is still the object of theological and philosophical debate, largely within the Christian, Jewish, and Islamic traditions. As Leibniz presents this version of the dilemma: "It is generally agreed that whatever God wills is good and just. But there remains the question whether it is good and just because God wills it or whether God wills it because it is good and just; in other words, whether justice and goodness are arbitrary or whether they belong to the necessary and eternal truths about the nature of things."

Explanation of the dilemma

The first horn

The first horn of the dilemma (i.e. that which is right is commanded by God because it is right) goes under a variety of names: intellectualism, rationalism, realism, and/or naturalism. Roughly, it is the view is that there are independent moral standards: some actions are right or wrong in themselves, independently of God's commands. As seen above, this is the view accepted by Socrates and Euthyphro in Plato's dialogue. The Mu'tazilah school of Islamic theology also defended the view, with some (e.g., Nazzam) maintaining that God is powerless to engage in injustice or lying. Though Aquinas never explicitly addresses the Euthyphro dilemma, interpreters often put him on this side of the issue. Aquinas draws a distinction between what is good or evil in itself and what is good or evil because of God's commands, with unchangeable moral standards forming the bulk of natural law. Thus he contends that not even God can change the Ten Commandments (adding that God can change what individuals deserve in particular cases, in what might look like special dispensations to murder or steal). Among later Scholastics, Vásquez is particularly clear-cut about obligations coming prior to anyone's will, even God's. Modern natural law theory saw Grotius and Leibniz also putting morality prior to God's will, comparing moral truths to unchangeable mathematical truths, and engaging voluntarists like Pufendorf in philosophical controversy. Cambridge Platonists like Benjamin Whichcote and Ralph Cudworth mounted seminal attacks on voluntarist theories, paving the way for the later rationalist metaethics of Samuel Clarke and Richard Price: what emerged was a view on which eternal moral standards (though dependent on God in some way) exist independently of God's will and prior to God's commands. Contemporary philosophers of religion who take this horn of the Euthyphro dilemma include Richard Swinburne and T. J. Mawson (though see below for complications).

Problems

This horn of the dilemma faces several problems:

  • Sovereignty: If there are moral standards independent of God's will, then "[t]here is something over which God is not sovereign. God is bound by the laws of morality instead of being their establisher. Moreover, God depends for his goodness on the extent to which he conforms to an independent moral standard. Thus, God is not absolutely independent." 18th-century philosopher Richard Price, who takes the first horn and thus sees morality as "necessary and immutable", sets out the objection as follows: "It may seem that this is setting up something distinct from God, which is independent of him, and equally eternal and necessary."
  • Omnipotence: These moral standards would limit God's power: not even God could oppose them by commanding what is evil and thereby making it good. As Richard Swinburne puts the point, this horn "seems to place a restriction on God's power if he cannot make any action which he chooses obligatory... [and also] it seems to limit what God can command us to do. God, if he is to be God, cannot command us to do what, independently of his will, is wrong." This point was very influential in Islamic theology: "In relation to God, objective values appeared as a limiting factor to His power to do as He wills... Ash'ari got rid of the whole embarrassing problem by denying the existence of objective values which might act as a standard for God's action." Similar concerns drove the medieval voluntarists Scotus and Ockham.
  • Freedom of the will: Moreover, these moral standards would limit God's freedom of will: God could not command anything opposed to them, and perhaps would have no choice but to command in accordance with them. As Mark Murphy puts the point, "if moral requirements existed prior to God's willing them, requirements that an impeccable God could not violate, God's liberty would be compromised."
  • Morality without God: If there are moral standards independent of God, then morality would retain its authority even if God did not exist. This conclusion was explicitly (and notoriously) drawn by early modern political theorist Hugo Grotius: "What we have been saying [about the natural law] would have a degree of validity even if we should concede that which cannot be conceded without the utmost wickedness, that there is no God, or that the affairs of men are of no concern to him" On such a view, God is no longer a "law-giver" but at most a "law-transmitter" who plays no vital role in the foundations of morality. Nontheists have capitalized on this point, largely as a way of disarming moral arguments for God's existence: if morality does not depend on God in the first place, such arguments stumble at the starting gate.

The second horn

The second horn of the dilemma (i.e. that which is right is right because it is commanded by God) is sometimes known as divine command theory or voluntarism. Roughly, it is the view that there are no moral standards other than God's will: without God's commands, nothing would be right or wrong. This view was partially defended by Scotus, in arguing that not all Ten Commandments belong to the natural law. Scotus held that while our duties to God (found on the first tablet) are self-evident, true by definition, and unchangeable even by God, our duties to others (found on the second tablet) were arbitrarily willed by God and are within his power to revoke and replace (which is why God was able to command the murder of Isaac, the spoiling of the Egyptians, and the adulterous marriage of Hosea). Ockham went further, contending that (since there is no contradiction in it) God could command us not to love God and even to hate God. Later Scholastics like Pierre D'Ailly and his student Jean de Gerson explicitly confronted the Euthyphro dilemma, taking the voluntarist position that God does not "command good actions because they are good or prohibit evil ones because they are evil; but... these are therefore good because they are commanded and evil because prohibited." Protestant reformers Martin Luther and John Calvin both stressed the absolute sovereignty of God's will, with Luther writing that "for [God's] will there is no cause or reason that can be laid down as a rule or measure for it", and Calvin writing that "everything which [God] wills must be held to be righteous by the mere fact of his willing it." The voluntarist emphasis on God's absolute power was carried further by Descartes, who notoriously held that God had freely created the eternal truths of logic and mathematics, and that God was therefore capable of giving circles unequal radii, giving triangles other than 180 internal degrees, and even making contradictions true. Descartes explicitly seconded Ockham on hating God: "why should [God] not have been able to give this command [i.e., the command to hate God] to one of his creatures?" Hobbes notoriously reduced the justice of God to "irresistible power" (drawing the complaint of Bishop Bramhall that this "overturns... all law"). And Paley held that all moral obligations bottom out in the self-interested "urge" to avoid hell and enter heaven by acting in accord with God's commands. Islam's Ash'arite theologians, al-Ghazali foremost among them, accepted voluntarism: scholar George Hourani writes that the view "was probably more prominent and widespread in Islam than in any other civilization." Today divine command theory is defended by many philosophers of religion, though typically in a moderate form (see below).

Problems

This horn of the dilemma also faces several problems:

  • No reasons for morality: If there is no moral standard other than God's will, then God's commands are arbitrary (i.e., based on pure whimsy or caprice). This would mean that morality is ultimately not based on reasons: "if theological voluntarism is true, then God's commands/intentions must be arbitrary; [but] it cannot be that morality could wholly depend on something arbitrary... [for] when we say that some moral state of affairs obtains, we take it that there is a reason for that moral state of affairs obtaining rather than another." And as Michael J. Murray and Michael Rea put it, this would also "cas[t] doubt on the notion that morality is genuinely objective."
  • No reasons for God: This arbitrariness would also jeopardize God's status as a wise and rational being, one who always acts on good reasons only. As Leibniz writes: "Where will be his justice and his wisdom if he has only a certain despotic power, if arbitrary will takes the place of reasonableness, and if in accord with the definition of tyrants, justice consists in that which is pleasing to the most powerful? Besides it seems that every act of willing supposes some reason for the willing and this reason, of course, must precede the act."
  • Anything goes: This arbitrariness would also mean that anything could become good, and anything could become bad, merely upon God's command. Thus if God commanded us "to gratuitously inflict pain on each other" or to engage in "cruelty for its own sake" or to hold an "annual sacrifice of randomly selected ten-year-olds in a particularly gruesome ritual that involves excruciating and prolonged suffering for its victims," then we would be morally obligated to do so. As 17th-century philosopher Ralph Cudworth put it: "nothing can be imagined so grossly wicked, or so foully unjust or dishonest, but if it were supposed to be commanded by this omnipotent Deity, must needs upon that hypothesis forthwith become holy, just, and righteous."
  • Moral contingency: If morality depends on the perfectly free will of God, morality would lose its necessity: "If nothing prevents God from loving things that are different from what God actually loves, then goodness can change from world to world or time to time. This is obviously objectionable to those who believe that claims about morality are, if true, necessarily true." In other words, no action has its moral status necessarily: any right action could have easily been wrong, if God had so decided, and an action which is right today could easily become wrong tomorrow, if God so decides. Indeed, some have argued that divine command theory is incompatible with ordinary conceptions of moral supervenience.
  • Why do God's commands obligate?: Mere commands do not create obligations unless the commander has some commanding authority. But this commanding authority cannot itself be based on those very commands (i.e., a command to obey one's own commands), otherwise a vicious circle results. So, in order for God's commands to obligate us, he must derive commanding authority from some source other than his own will. As Cudworth put it: "For it was never heard of, that any one founded all his authority of commanding others, and others (sic) obligation or duty to obey his commands, in a law of his own making, that men should be required, obliged, or bound to obey him. Wherefore since the thing willed in all laws is not that men should be bound or obliged to obey; this thing cannot be the product of the meer (sic) will of the commander, but it must proceed from something else; namely, the right or authority of the commander". To avoid the circle, one might say our obligation comes from gratitude to God for creating us. But this presupposes some sort of independent moral standard obligating us to be grateful to our benefactors. As 18th-century philosopher Francis Hutcheson writes: "Is the Reason exciting to concur with the Deity this, 'The Deity is our Benefactor?' Then what Reason excites to concur with Benefactors?" Or finally, one might resort to Hobbes's view: "The right of nature whereby God reigneth over men, and punisheth those that break his laws, is to be derived, not from his creating them (as if he required obedience, as of gratitude for his benefits), but from his irresistible power." In other words, might makes right.
  • God's goodness: If all goodness is a matter of God's will, then what shall become of God's goodness? Thus William P. Alston writes, "since the standards of moral goodness are set by divine commands, to say that God is morally good is just to say that he obeys his own commands... that God practises what he preaches, whatever that might be", and Hutcheson deems such a view "an insignificant Tautology, amounting to no more than this, 'That God wills what he wills.'" Alternatively, as Leibniz puts it, divine command theorists "deprive God of the designation good: for what cause could one have to praise him for what he does, if in doing something quite different he would have done equally well?". A related point is raised by C. S. Lewis: "if good is to be defined as what God commands, then the goodness of God Himself is emptied of meaning and the commands of an omnipotent fiend would have the same claim on us as those of the 'righteous Lord.'" Or again Leibniz: "this opinion would hardly distinguish God from the devil." That is, since divine command theory trivializes God's goodness, it is incapable of explaining the difference between God and an all-powerful demon.
  • The is-ought problem and the naturalistic fallacy: According to David Hume, it is hard to see how moral propositions featuring the relation ought could ever be deduced from ordinary is propositions, such as "the being of a God". Divine command theory is thus guilty of deducing moral oughts from ordinary uses about God's commands. In a similar vein, G. E. Moore argued (with his open question argument) that the notion good is indefinable, and any attempts to analyze it in naturalistic or metaphysical terms are guilty of the so-called "naturalistic fallacy". This would block any theory which analyzes morality in terms of God's will: and indeed, in a later discussion of divine command theory, Moore concluded that "when we assert any action to be right or wrong, we are not merely making an assertion about the attitude of mind towards it of any being or set of beings whatever".
  • No morality without God: If all morality is a matter of God's will, then if God does not exist, there is no morality. This is the thought captured in the slogan (often attributed to Dostoevsky) "If God does not exist, everything is permitted." Divine command theorists disagree over whether this is a problem for their view or a virtue of their view. Many would argue that morality does indeed require God's existence, and that this is in fact a problem for atheism. But divine command theorist Robert M. Adams contends that this idea ("that no actions would be ethically wrong if there were not a loving God") is one that "will seem (at least initially) implausible to many", and that his theory must "dispel [an] air of paradox."

My YouTube Video

Santa Monica Evangelism—01/30/10

Last night's engagements at Santa Monica were very fruitful. It was a little different given the large pockets of conversations that were happening on the sidelines. I was very comforted to see what was going on. Different people even came up to me and asked me questions about Islam and I was happy to direct them to my website.

On a different note, however, was the conversation about Law or Torah—the first five books of Moses. The last conversation—or I should say the last question that was asked—had to do with the keeping of the Sabbath. It is important to discuss issues that pertain to theology, but the nature of the question was very different in that the young man wanted to know what saved him. I think he was depending on his works, i.e., keep the Sabbath, which he claimed warrants to say that he could be saved by keeping it. Personally I think Luis and the young man were speaking past each other. The young man, concerned with the Law, was asking why Christians do not keep the Sabbath. I too would ask that question in light of the third use of the law. Men, theologians, of good repute—e.g., Luther, Calvin and Olivian, to name a few—all held that the Sabbath is a moral decree, not only ceromonial. I think the primary confusion was about the application of the moral law under its third use. In this sense I would have to disagree with TruthDefenders, and at this juncture I am going to appeal to my confessional standards:

WCF 21.8—This Sabbath is to be kept holy unto the Lord when men after a due preparing of their hearts and ordering of their common affairs beforehand do not only observe an holy rest all the day from their own works words and thoughts about their wordly employments and recreations but also are taken up the whole time in the public and private exercises of His worship and in the duties of necessity and mercy.

Now this is an issue for debate, but it is intramural and should not be employed while we preach the evangelical gospel once delivered to saints (Jude 4). As a polemical issue I think that I take issue with some interpretations of this article, but like I said it is intramural for the Reformed community. I don't expect anyone who is not covenantal to hold to this view. My main aim in this blog is mainly to update people about the gospel as it is preached in Santa Monica. Polemical issues, though important, are hard to deal with in a quick conversation on the mic. It should be noted that notes and papers have been written by myself with due diligence in research, however limited for the purposes of evangelizing, and by others as well. If anyone wishes to debate these issues, I think the best way to talk about them is through email interchange or even forum boards, which are available (see the PuritanBoard website). Santa Monica is not a platform for a thorough discourse of theology or whatever view. It is primarily for evangelism.

Angel was causing havoc once again. (Boy he annoys me!) I also got to meet some nice people from Hope. I really enjoy their zeal for evangelism. I was able to give a young man some materials that he could pick up on eschatology—a personal favorite of mine.

As far as the Lord's Day is concerned, it was an awesome message. Ron preached a great sermon. It really got me thinking about servitude and the example Jesus laid down for Christians to follow. Covenant theology part in parcel was also discussed this morning in the catechism class (WSC Q7-Q10). We talked about the indicative/imperative perceptive will of God, which also branches into the Law/Gospel distinction in covenant theology. Finally, we celebrated the Lord's Table this morning. I loved it! Great morning today.

Monday, January 25, 2010

There Really Isn’t Anything New Under the Sun

I found this article online about the impending ruling on Prop. 8—yes, I know…again. I thought this should shed some light of the real trajectory this case has been going, specifically of those of the opposite side.

Forget the law. Chief U.S. District Judge Vaughn Walker has allowed the trial over a challenge to overturn Proposition 8 - the 2008 California ballot initiative that limited marriage to "a man and a woman" and was approved by 52 percent of California voters - to turn into what the measure's opponents like to call a "teachable moment." That's another way of saying that the law isn't as important as feelings in this trial.[1]

Clearly a stymie approach to politics. I wonder how the debate would go if the tables were turned. I assume they would be saying, "You lost. Get over it." Likewise! You lost. Get over it!

[1] http://www.sfgate.com/cgi-bin/article.cgi?f=/c/a/2010/01/23/ING61BKAMP.DTL. Emphasis mine.

Monday, January 11, 2010

Resources on Free Speech and Evangelism in the Public Square

Courtesy of Truth Defenders

(Note to all: Reformed Piety & Ethics did not put this together. I just merged all the blog accounts under one name. I am giving credit, however, to those responsible for the research.)

"The Truth Shall Make You Free" John 8: 32

Many Christians are hindered from openly declaring the Glorious Gospel of the Lord Jesus Christ because of fear. A fear that comes from ignorance of the law concerning their rights. This blogger has been set up to educate and encouraged my fellow brothers and sisters in Christ to openly share their faith.

By the sovereign grace of the True and Living God of Abraham, Isaac, and Jacob, these rights are extended to all who wish to exercise them. May the faithful servant of God take advantage of these rights while they still exist, for the time will come when the lights of freedom will no longer shine and we will be forced to join the underground church, as many of our brothers and sisters are now in many of the closed and communist countries.

Supreme Court Rulings:

U.S. Iowa, 1969: Undifferentiated fear or apprehension of disturbance is not enough to overcome right to freedom of expression.[1]

Also, see identical ruling, Federal District Court, Texas, 1969:[2]

Federal Court of Appeals, Florida, 1972: Hostile audience is not basis for restraining otherwise legal first amendment activity.[3]

Federal Court of Appeals, Florida, 1974: Public expression of ideas may not be prohibited merely because ideas are themselves of offensive to some of their hearers.[4]

Federal Court of Appeals, Indiana, 1974: Freedom of expression (does not mean freedom to express only approved ideas; it means freedom to express any idea.[5]

Federal Court of Appeals, District of Colubia, 1977: The Constitution mandates that access to the streets, sidewalks, parks, and other similar public places for purpose of exercising first amendment rights cannot be denied broadly and absolutely.[6]

United States District Court, E.D. Wisconsin, April 30, 1970: An ordinance that proscribes conduct that tends to "disturb or annoy others" is both vague and overbroad. I he constitutionally protected exercise of free expression frequently causes a disturbance, for the very purpose of the first amendment is to stimulate the creation and communication of new, and therefore, often controversial ideas. The prohibition against conduct that tends to disturb another would literally make it a crime to deliver an unpopular speech that resulted in a "disturbance." Such a restriction is a clearly invalid restriction of constitutionally protected free expression.[7]

Federal District Court, Tennessee, 1978: The fact that persons might express their religious views at some place other than the public streets, sidewalks, and other areas of the city does not have any consequence in determining the validity of permit requirements with respect to the use of such public areas.[8]

Federal Court of Appeals, Virginia, 1982: Reasonable time, place, and manner restrictions on free expression and their enforcement cannot he based on content of speech thereby restricted.

A compelling governmental interest unrelated to speech must he served by restriction on speech.

Ordinance containing restrictions on free expression must be drawn with narrow specificity to be no more restrictive than necessary to secure such interest.

Adequate alternative channels of communication must be left open by restrictions on free expression.[9]

Federal Court of Appeals, Virginia, 1973: The first amendment protects from state interference the expression in a public place of the unpopular as well as the popular and the right to assemble peaceably in a public place in the interest and furtherance of the unpopular as well as the popular.[10]

Federal Court of Appeals, Virginia, 1972: Government may not favor one religion over another.[11]

U.S., Arkansas, 1968: The freedom of religion provision of the first amendment forbids alike the preference of a religious doctrine or the prohibition of a theory which is deemed antagonistic to a particular dogma. The state has no legitimate interest in protecting any or all religions from views distasteful to them.[12]

Federal Court of Appeals, Texas, 1972: "Controversy" is never sufficient in and of itself to stifle the views of any citizen.[13]

U.S, California, 1971: As a general matter, the establishment clause of the first amendment prohibits government from abandoning secular purposes in order to put an imprimatur on one religion, or on religion as such, or to favor the adherence of any sect or religious organization.[14]

Having established the Supreme Court rulings being in favor of free speech, we hereby freely express our understanding; that all religious, non-religious, political, philosophical, public or private world views and practices that conflict with Holy Writ are in error and may put one in danger of hellfire if not repented of. Repentance is the turning from sin to the True and Living God through his Son Jesus the Christ as revealed in the Holy Scriptures (the Bible).

Feel free to copy and distribute this list of rights to anyone involved in evangelistic ministries.

ATTENTION: It is important that you realize that the law changes frequently, it is your responsibility to be sure that you are acting within the current laws in your state or district.

END NOTES

  1. U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. I (Tinker v. Des Moines Independent Community School Dist. 89 S. Ct. 733, 393/ U.S. 53/21 L. Eid. 2d. 731).
  2. (Calbillo v. San Jancinto Junior College, 305 F. Supp. 857, cause remanded 434 F. 2d. 609, appeal after remand 446 F. 2d. 887).
  3. U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. I (Collie v. Chicago Park Dist., 460 F. 2d. 746).
  4. West's F.S.A. 877.03; U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. I (Wiegand v. Seaver, 504 F. 2d. 303).
  5. (Perry v. Columbia Broadcasting System, Inc. 499 F. 2d. 797).
  6. U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. I (Washington Mobilization Committee v. Cullinane, 566 F. 2d. 107, 184 U. S. App. D. C. 215).
  7. (Gardner v. Ceci, 312 F. Supp. 516/ see also Landry v. Daley, 280 F. Supp. 968, N.D. 111. 1968).
  8. U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. I (Smith v. City of Manchester, 460 F. Supp. 30).
  9. Davenport v. City of Alexandria, Virginia, 683 F. 2d. 853, on rehearing 710 F. 2d. 148. Also, see Salahuddin v. Carlson, 523 F. Supp. 314.).
  10. U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. I (National Socialist White People's Party v. Ringers, 473 F. 2d. 1010).
  11. U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. I (U.S. v. Crowthers, 456 F. 2d. 1074).
  12. U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. I (Epperson v. State of Arkansas, 89 S. Ct. 266).
  13. U.S.C.A. Const. Amend. I (Shanlcy v. Northeast Independent School Dist., Bexar County, Texas, 462 F. 2d. 960).
  14. U.S.C.A. Const. Amed. I (Negre v. Larsen, 91 S. Ct. 828).

News Update on Last Week’s Santa Monica Evangelism

We had a great turn out this last Saturday. Truth Defender's own, Luis Zepeda, and myself got there early to see our fellow brothers in the faith, Tom and Chris, evangelize. This was the first time I had actually gone up to speak, however short that stint turned out. I hope to see more of it this coming week. I met another girl who claimed to be a Christian who asked some very probing questions about God's love and God's justice. (Coming from a Reformed perspective, I love hearing these sorts of questions. It puts me in the hot seat.) Somehow some Christians have this weird notion about God's love that doesn't comport at all with orthodox doctrine (e.g., God either loves all or he doesn't love at all). I didn't give her a hard time, though, but I did ask her questions about justice and what she thinks God's justice superimposes on personal ethics. I wasn't surprised when I heard her answer about homosexuality. Because of her answer, I am finishing up some slides about God's justice.

Louis had a great turn out. There were a couple of female Muslims who were getting out of control. I wasn't surprised by the way they responded. Louis did an amazing job, however, in showing them that calling them "evil" or "sinful" were not strictly speaking his own personal epithets. He showed that it was said by Islam's so-called prophet, pedophile Mohammad. I thought it was pretty funny that she said, "Islaaaam" (the way she said it was so funny. I thought she was trying too hard to make it sound Arabic, as if that added to its truthfulness) is a peaceful religion. Let's not look at Wahabist interpretations, mind you, so that we can infer this kind of buffoonery. Given that Islam's most conservative sect, Sunni Islam, does not grant this interpretation, then I think I will consider them more authoritative than this ignorant yet pop-culture Islam, which is no Islam at all.

HOT OFF THE PRESSES

"The museum said the controversial images—objected to by conservative Muslims who say their religion forbids images of their holy founder—were 'under review.'" (New York Post Jan. 10.)

If this isn't "worship" in the strictest sense, then I don't know what is.

Thursday, January 07, 2010

Calvinism and Pseudo Christianity

I'm proud to say that the new slides for my presentation are looking good. I'm trying to draft a logo for my website, so if anyone knows of an artist send them my way. Anyway, the new slides mainly have to do with a Christian response to why we—Reformed Piety & Ethics and Truth Defenders—do what we do, namely to witness/evangelize to people in the public square. I think these slides will at least mitigate some of the unjustified retorts that I hear from empty-headed Christians who don't know the Bible from their rear. My slides mainly deal with Biblical anthropology and Calvinism, since they are inseparable in my point of view. I mainly do a roundabout survey of N. Geisler's book, Chosen but Free, and James White response to Dr. Geisler, The Potter's Freedom.

I'm mainly touching this subject because of the constant criticisms Christians have been leveling against Truth Defenders. Because of the ignorance of the opposite side, I have sought to list some good sources that I think will be helpful in evaluating the debate with "simple" Christians who read nothing "but the Bible." I say that tongue-in-cheek pejoratively, since this statement is actually contrary to what the Bible commands, namely to show oneself approved, well-rounded and educated in every area of study—therefore illustrating the very definition of world view apologetics. It may sound offensive, but honesty is certainly the best policy here.

Sunday, January 03, 2010

Sunday School Class

Day 1: Westminster Shorter Catechism at Grace Presbyterian Church

By Julio Martinez Jr.

Great discussions this morning. I got my booklet for the class and I'm glad to say that it's going to be a great class. Today we talked about the church and missiology. I had a couple questions about that, but unfortunately Ron couldn't answer them because of time constraints. I'm happy to know, however, that as Presbyterians we affirm the dominion mandate and in effect, the mandate to "Christianize" the world. To the dismay of many evangelicals, however, there is a growing "intellectual promiscuity"[1] that is plaguing the church worldwide.

Christians are dumbing down and are therefore ill-equipped for that very task, i.e., evangelization. Just this last Saturday, there were a couple of Latino Christians (allegedly Christian) who opposed the preaching of the gospel. This really caused me to scratch my head in confusion, seeing that there is ample evidence to the contrary in the Old[2] and New Testament Scriptures. (It apparently was nebulous to read the sign in front of them which states to withhold personal critiques from Christians publicly. It seems like this discipline called reading is very strange!) In effect, I have made it my aim to finish a book called "Beyond the Bounds" in order to respond to these sorts of remarks. I intend on making my findings into slides on PowerPoint. (I might just turn it into a pamphlet as well, but I digress.)

Back on point. We, the church, are now embarking on a study of the Westminster Shorter Catechism—in my view, one of the best catechisms in all of Christendom. We only covered the introduction to the class, which aimed at the telos of the class—or the general purpose of the class—which is growth in grace, understanding and stewardship, all of which define Reformed Piety & Ethics.

NOTES

[1] I wrote a scathing letter to the catholic (universal) church concerning her promiscuity and urge her to action. My letter can be found on my WordPress titled, "Intellectual Promiscuity: A Letter to the Reserved Christian." <http://jmartinez83.wordpress.com/2008/07/12/intellectual-promiscuity—letter-to-the-reserved-christian/>

[2] For the Old Testament passages, see Bahnsen's "For Whom was the Law Intended." It can be found online at http://cmfnow.com under the free articles. If you're interested in the article, just email me at jmartinez.reformed@gmail.com. I'll be happy to forward the material.